MENU

The “Corporation” Is Pro-Individualism and Pro-Capitalism

By Vinay Kolhatkar

July 16, 2019

SUBSCRIBE TO SAVVY STREET (It's Free)

 

“Am I getting through to you, Mr. Beale? You get up on your little 21-inch screen and howl about America and democracy. There is no America. There is no democracy. There is only IBM, and ITT, and AT&T, and DuPont, Dow, Union Carbide, and Exxon. We no longer live in a world of nations and ideologies, Mr. Beale. The world is a college of corporations.” – ­­Arthur Jensen, Network (1976)

Big corporations are certainly sizeable, with top-ranked Microsoft exceeding a trillion dollars in market capitalization (value of each share times the number of shares outstanding) in June 2019. Facebook was fifth at over half a trillion dollars in value, and Amazon, Apple Inc., and Alphabet (Google’s parent company) were ranked second to fourth.

The sheer size of some multinational corporations scares many people, like the fictional Arthur Jensen, into conspiracy theories. Are large corporations more influential than nations? Do they control politicians or is it the other way around?

However, these days, even for-profit corporations aspire to be good “corporate citizens,” doing their bit for the environment, the community, and social justice. Is it only lip service? More importantly, do such businesses have a right, let alone an obligation, to behave like benevolent organizations?

To answer these questions, we must first understand the nature of the corporation.
 

The Theory of the “Corporation”

In 1970, Milton Friedman asserted, in the Times no less (how the times have changed), that:

There is one and only one social responsibility of business—to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules of the game, which is to say, engages in open and free competition without deception [or] fraud.

The corporation, said Friedman, has no social responsibility:

If this statement [that the corporate executive has social responsibility] is not pure rhetoric, it must mean that he is to act in some way that is not in the interest of his employers. For example, that he is to refrain from increasing the price of the product in order to contribute to the social objective of preventing inflation, even though a price increase would be in the best interests of the corporation. Or that he is to make expenditures on reducing pollution beyond the amount that is in the best interests of the corporation or that is required by law in order to contribute to the social objective of improving the environment. Or that, at the expense of corporate profits, he is to hire ‘hardcore’ unemployed instead of better-qualified available workmen to contribute to the social objective of reducing poverty.

In each of these cases, the corporate executive would be spending someone else’s money for a general social interest. Insofar as his actions in accord with his ‘social responsibility’ reduce returns to stockholders, he is spending their money.

Friedman was interpreted as implying that executives are merely the servants of the shareholders.

Are they?

In 2005, John Mackey, CEO of Whole Foods, disagreed with Friedman:

I’m a businessman and a free market libertarian, but I believe that the enlightened corporation should try to create value for all of its constituencies.

I believe the entrepreneurs, not the current investors in a company’s stock, have the right and responsibility to define the purpose of the company. It is the entrepreneurs who create a company, who bring all the factors of production together and coordinate it into viable business. It is the entrepreneurs who set the company strategy and who negotiate the terms of trade with all of the voluntarily cooperating stakeholders–including the investors. At Whole Foods we “hired” our original investors. They didn’t hire us.

Friedman countered that view:

The social responsibility of business to increase its profits and Mackey’s statement that “the enlightened corporation should try to create value for all of its constituencies” are equivalent.

It may well be in the long run interest of a corporation that is a major employer in a small community to devote resources to providing amenities to that community or to improving its government.

T.J. Rodgers, founder and CEO of Cypress Semiconductors, was more scathing of Mackey:

Mackey spouts nonsense about how his company hired his original investors, not vice versa. If Whole Foods ever falls on persistent hard times–perhaps when the Luddites are no longer able to hold back the genetic food revolution using junk science and fear–he will quickly find out who has hired whom, as his investors fire him.

However, Mackey does not lose sight of investors in his “profits are a means to a mission” defense of making a mission the primary purpose of a corporation.

In economic literature, Friedman’s tenet is referred to as shareholder primacy. In 2002, Professor Stephen Bainbridge offered an alternative “director primacy” view that put the Board in control. Mackey’s view could be termed as entrepreneur or management primacy. However, in each case, we have some class in ultimate control, suggestive of a master-servant relationship. But need there be any primacy at all?

The Corporation is a nexus of contracts.

To gauge who is right or wrong here, it’s illuminating to go back to the Seventies. In 1976, professors Michael Jensen and William Meckling wrote one of the most seminal phrases in all of finance theory by revisiting the concept of the firm as a system of relationships (which was extant in academe since the Thirties)—the Corporation, they said, is a “nexus of contracts.”

And, in a free society, such contracts would be entered into voluntarily by individuals, whether that be a contract between a cleaner and a cleaning company, or between an office-cleaning company and a large multinational, or between a CEO and a large corporation.

Mackey may have originally sought investors for an idea, but he is wrong to generalize the investor class as passive—private-equity investors often seek operating management severely constrained by tight contracts, while themselves setting corporate strategy. He is also wrong to assume he “hired” investors. He invited investors to contract with him, i.e., hire him as CEO to pursue a vision, including a return for investors, articulated by him, and some investors voluntarily agreed to do so. In the subsequent “contract,” the firm as a legal entity (the nexus) hired him as CEO, and that set forth the future relationship, even if Mackey initiated the invitation.

To illustrate, if I agree to buy your used car, it matters not who made the first approach once a contract is executed—the contract sets out our rights and obligations going forward.

The Value within Corporations

A firm typically seeks synergy in the contractual bundle that it acquires—the whole is more than the sum of its parts. As accountants and economists know, the going-concern value of a firm will most often exceed the value in bankruptcy from a fire-sale asset sell-off.

Further, as theorists Ayotte and Hansmann note in “A nexus of contracts theory of legal entities”:

A legal entity permits an owner to create a firm as a bundle of contracts that can be transferred to someone else, but only if they are transferred together. This bundled assignability allows for a balancing of several potentially conflicting interests.

The firm’s value is unchanged by changes in passive ownership occurring almost incessantly via trading on a stock exchange. But stakeholders will often contract via the firm as a nexus to retain key executives with incentives and penalties. Lenders seek to prevent the unbundling and the selling off of valuable subsidiary rights in the nexus via warranties in the contract for debt.

Thus, one way to characterize what I would call a POPL (a privately-owned, publicly-listed) corporation, is as a synergistic bundle of contracts, alienable from its current owners whose liability is limited to sunk cost or investment contracted for, and assignable as a bundle.

The limited-liability corporation device is a visionary invention of the modern economic era. Its essence is pro-individualism and pro-laissez-faire Capitalism.

The limited-liability corporation device is a visionary invention of the modern economic era. It has significantly advanced private enterprise by merging economies of scale with labor specialization and voluntary contracting among individuals. Its essence is pro-individualism and pro-laissez-faire Capitalism. There is nothing intrinsic to its nature that requires it to be a crony of the State.

But we do not live in free societies. In Crony Capitalism in America, author Hunter Lewis asserts that “cronyism is as old as recorded human history”—which he states is “precisely why the human race has made so little progress in overcoming poverty.” Lewis contends that only in the 18th and 19th centuries were there positive reforms, and only the U.S., Europe, and Japan benefited from such reforms that set cronyism back. How does cronyism set in?

 

Intrusive Lawmaking Co-opts the Corporation to Serve the State

In 1978, professors Jensen and Meckling returned to the theme of voluntary contracting, celebrating the phenomenal economic progress of the previous 200 years, while bemoaning the erosion of property rights. They articulated the root cause of that erosion—Cronyism:

Bureaucrats and politicians can and do use their positions in government to bestow benefits on others, in exchange for votes, for campaign funds, for favors, for job offers, all of which yield benefits to themselves. Revocation and abrogation of rights is the currency in which politicians and bureaucrats deal. Like all of us, they are constantly searching for ways to expand the market for their services. To do so, they must effectively break down the system of private rights because it limits their market. Stability in private rights is, by its very nature, a constraint on what government (i.e., bureaucrats and politicians) can do.

Jensen and Meckling cite the case of Penn Central Railroad, a corporation that in their opinion was forced into bankruptcy by price-fixing and wage-control regulation that violated the prior voluntary contracting. Subsequently, bondholders’ contractual rights to seize assets were abrogated. “Like successful businessmen and successful academics, successful politicians are entrepreneurs, constantly at work marketing their product,” say Jensen and Meckling, illustrating that if a private utility is bankrupted by regulation, politicians declare a “crisis” and come to the rescue with public ownership, new public investment, or heavier regulation. This manufacturing of crises—energy, environmental, unemployment, immigration etc. provides opportunities to expand the role of the State in economic affairs, undermining property rights, investor trust, and creating economic inefficiency by subverting the price system.

Section 10 of Article 1 of the U.S. Constitution says: “No state shall make any law impairing the obligation of contracts.”

And the courts, Jensen and Meckling warn us, have not upheld contractual rights—even though Section 10 of Article 1 of the U.S. Constitution says: “No state shall make any law impairing the obligation of contracts,” and the Fifth Amendment provides that “No person shall be deprived of life, liberty or property without due process of law, nor shall private property be taken for public use, without just compensation.”

Where to, from Here?

Are we now helplessly flung into a chaotic slide of the West into Communism?

Probably not, because, rather than making it infrequent, intermittent, and unpredictable, an absolute violation of voluntary contracting is a road to the destruction of the price system and property rights—and that road leads to the economy of Venezuela. What the really smart politicians want is not a slaying of Atlas, but an incestuous relationship—hence we can predict that the political “Godfathers” will take no more than their “protection” money.

Behind the mask of the sovereign State lie individuals, seeking aggrandizement of their power, wealth, rank, and honor.

Behind the mask of the sovereign State lie individuals, seeking aggrandizement of their power, wealth, rank, and honor. Incapable of running the corporations profitably themselves, the bureaucrats let the producers have a little freedom to compete and produce, as long as they also do the bidding required of them, of being good “corporate citizens.”

It’s beautiful for the aggrandizers, isn’t it? Let them run … but keep them on a long, invisible leash. Not only will they produce goods and services, but they are the perfect “Fall Guys” for the blame game when things go wrong, and they even donate to your campaigns. Indeed, banks, by undertaking widespread “social-justice” home lending, sparked the global financial crisis, and they even meekly took the blame after the State-managed central banks ignited that spark into a raging inferno.

The end-game is not the U.S.S.R., but the new Russia of the billionaire oligarchs feasting on the private sector, granting and receiving favors, setting up an interdependency that the private sector cannot disentangle itself from.

 

Co-opting YouTube and Facebook into Censorship

Neo-Marxist philosophy has been advocated by much of the professoriate since the Sixties. Its new social strand is derived from the old Marxist notion of inevitable class wars, except that it sees these battles everywhere—race wars, gender exploitation, ethnic and national domination, and conflicts over sexuality. The U.N., the EU, and the media are all predominantly neo-Marxist as are most governments. And they need a tactic to bully corporates to be their agents of change without overtly making it appear so.

Is the concept of corporate social responsibility (CSR) a veil for such neo-Marxist intrusions?

In 2015, in his paper titled, “The politics of corporate social responsibility,” (subtitle: “Why Milton Friedman has been right all along”) Professor Marc Orlitzky’s findings were that “the literature review provides empirical support for Milton Friedman’s (1970) claim that the values underpinning CSR are driven by a socialist-collectivist agenda, which is inherently opposed to capitalist/libertarian values of free enterprise and individualism.”

In the 21st Century, the postmodern neo-Marxists also invaded the funds management industry.

In the 21st Century, the postmodern neo-Marxists also invaded the funds management industry. Words like “humane,” “ethical,” or “responsible” camouflage their real motive. Today, money managers are scrutinized for “responsible investment,” by entities that are not their clients, to pressure them into investments that seek “climate-change risk mitigation” and avoid “modern slavery.” ESG (environmental, social, and governance) investing is not a fad, it has $20 trillion allocated to it.

Corporations co-opted into semi-fascism shed their souls. Many also become as two-faced as their sovereign sugar daddies—they proclaim to take pride, not in profits, but in lip service to the green lobby, not in a meritocracy, but in multi-gender representation on their boards and management, not in free speech, but in engendering a narrative controlled by their political masters. But soon, just as Friedman predicted, their own rhetoric traps them.

“Hate speech” legislation has now been passed in several countries.

“Hate speech” legislation has now been passed in several countries, and its effect is to stifle expressions opposed to the U.N./EU’s postmodern neo-Marxist worldview by casting them as fake, racist, or xenophobic. Gatestone Institute informed its readers that “In 2017, Facebook’s Vice President of Public Policy, Joel Kaplan, reportedly agreed to requests from Pakistan’s Interior Minister Nisar Ali Khan, to ‘remove fake accounts and explicit, hateful and provocative material that incites violence and terrorism’ because “the entire Muslim Ummah was greatly disturbed ….”

German censorship laws now require social media platforms to delete any “alleged criminal offenses such as libel, slander, defamation or incitement, within 24 hours of receipt of a user complaint.” French regulators recently spent six months inside Facebook, assessing its hate-speech policies. President Macron now wants more oversight of social media. “Hate-speech” laws can even criminalize people who post information about the atrocities committed by terrorists. Among sovereigns, only the U.S. Supreme Court has thwarted hate-speech legislation’s intrusion into the American legal system.

So the platform providers maintain a right to unilaterally amend the conditions on which the platform is provided to retail clients—precisely to cater for such uncontrollable regulatory risk. In 2019, the EU even thanked Facebook, Google, and Twitter—for “cooperating” to remove “hate speech” from their platforms.

Now put yourself in the shoes of Mark Zuckerberg—it’s co-opt or die.

Now put yourself in the shoes of Mark Zuckerberg, or of the board members of Amazon, or Alphabet (which owns Google, which, in turn owns YouTube)—it’s co-opt or die. Indeed, as Hunter Lewis demonstrates, co-opting often put many corporations ahead of the regulatory curve—the incestuous step-children initiated competition-stifling regulation, and it was marketed by their sugar daddies as “protecting the consumers.” If today’s “John Mackey” wants his corporation to fulfill its corporate mission, not just profit, but getting into bed with sovereigns, is also a means—the Mafia-State’s offer of protection within its “sovereign boundaries” has become economically attractive—symbiotic even.

The Corporation is a device that bolsters the workings of the market, when it’s free. But the corporate device cannot be built to withstand an attack on the freedom of the market itself. Multinationals operate in several jurisdictions, and are subject to intrusive lawmaking that cannot be prevented in unfettered democracies, or in republics with inadequate constitutional protections, or when enshrined constitutional protections are not enforced by the courts.

Only the courts upholding a strong Constitution or an alert, active, and knowledgeable electorate can thwart the State from further encroachment. In the absence of that bulwark, the value and validity of contracts in the nexus of contracts are threatened, and before long, the nexus is subtly, almost unnoticeably, co-opted into a system of semi-Fascism.

The fictional character, Arthur Jensen, was wrong. There are nations and ideologies, and they require corporations, big and small, to heed them.
 

 

(Visited 631 times, 1 visits today)
   
0 0 votes
Article Rating
Subscribe
Notify of
4 Comments
Oldest
Newest Most Voted
Inline Feedbacks
View all comments
W.R. Donway
W.R. Donway
5 years ago

No battle today is more crucial than defense of corporation.

The modern corporation, especially the for-profit business corporation, emerged with the Industrial Revolution and capitalism. It is the single most powerful conception–and social creation–ever devised for entirely voluntary, freely chosen cooperation among an unlimited number of individuals acting for their own ends but in doing so contributing to success of everyone involved.

Born in an era of growing freedom from government, demands for human rights, and dismantling of the “society of status” enforced by government, the modern corporation was a triumph of the “society of contract”–freely chosen relationships and obligations. Indeed, the corporation in our time has been defined as “a nexus of contracts.” It is the realization of the dream that any productive goal, however immensely ambitious, whatever time might be required, whatever resources needed, can be achieved without forcing anyone’s participation.

It is not wonder socialists of every stripe view the business corporation of the enemy.

Almost from the start, the corporation came under attack, first from the status society of aristocracy and privilege, then from every variant of socialist planning for government ownership of property, government regulation of production, government regulation of labor, and government disposal of all production. In our time, the corporation is torn between the demands of politicians and bureaucrats–satisfied to control it, tax it to fund giveaways to voters, and “share the wealth” through campaign contributions and bribes–and an amalgam of postmodernists, globalists, and environmentalists who view the corporation as the ultimate repository of capitalism’s selfish power, a power that must be forced to serve an endless and engulfing “social agenda.”

Whatever their goal or guise, all attacks on the corporation are directed at its fundamental, defining characteristic: namely, freely entered contractual arrangements for freely chosen goals pursued for mutual benefit. It is the diametrical opposite of all forms of socialism, communistic or fascistic, which dictate all goals, roles, and relationships to achieve the mandated “collective good.”

In the battle for the corporation, the metaphysical requirements of human survival–the individual’s freedom of thought and action–clash directly and fundamentally with the postmodernist vision of “social” (i.e., government) control over the human hive to chase goals such as guaranteed incomes, global climate control, and equal statistical outcomes from all races.

CharlesRAnderson
CharlesRAnderson
5 years ago

Prof. David Mayer wrote a very good book called Liberty of Contract — Rediscovering a lost constitutional right, published by Cato Institute, 2011. Check it out.

Vinay Kolhatkar
5 years ago

Thank you.

CharlesRAnderson
CharlesRAnderson
5 years ago

There are two statements in which sovereign is associated with states or government. In one the phrase is the behind the mask of sovereignty, which might acknowledge that the state tends to make a pretense of being sovereign. The other starts off “Among sovereigns, only the U.S. Supreme Court ….”, appears to actually grant sovereignty to governments.

States or governments are never sovereign — they are at best legitimate. The individual is sovereign and rights reside only in the individual. The legitimacy of government is derived from its protection of the many and broad sovereign rights of the individuals within its territory of operation. It is this individual rights protection service that justifies the existence of government. To say that a government or state is sovereign is the equivalent of saying that all rights reside in the government and the state hands out such privileges as it sees fit to individuals. Those privileges can be revoked at the whim of the sovereign state. The sovereign state demands that the people serve it, while the sovereign individual demands that the state serve each and every individual. There is a world of difference.

Joe Biden has explicitly embraced the sovereign state that grants such privileges as it chooses to individuals and denies the sovereignty of individuals and their pre-state assertion of rights which governments are formed to protect. This viewpoint highly dominates those of the Democratic Party and is also held by quite a few Republicans. It is the basis for the belief that it is a proper function of the government to do harm to some as long as it can claim it is doing good for more people than or harmed or that it is doing good for the “least among us.” This viewpoint removes sovereignty from the individual and effectively removes all of his rights, while opening the floodgates on an endless list of government powers. The only real limit on government power is that it is only legitimate to the degree that it protects the exercise of each and every individual’s rights.

A corporation is a vehicle enabling a complex network of cooperative associations among many people. A nexus of contracts is certainly part of its nature. That part is commonly quite explicit in many larger corporations, but is much less so in many small corporations. The constant is the network of cooperative associations among individuals, which a good society allows to be voluntary associations. Other business forms are also composed of a network of cooperative associations among individuals. When government goes after businesses, it is because it wants to interfere with these voluntary cooperative associations. It wants to force them to change in ways that make them serve the government’s purposes. The fact that these networks of cooperative associations are very complex makes it relatively easy for governments and its hosts of cronies to confuse large numbers of voters into supporting their attacks on businesses.

test